Can we hold theory fixed for a minute?

In the current PS, Luke Keele (link) makes a great point about the need for journals to let researchers take existing theories and subject them to multiple rounds of empirical scrutiny:

Of course, there is nothing wrong with new theories;
however, I believe that an overemphasis on theory can
impede the ability of the discipline to establish causal
relationships. One point of emphasis in the identification
revolution is that causal inference is difficult. A series of
regression models is hardly the last word in whether a causal
theory holds. Within causal inference, it is generally understood
that only a series of different studies using disparate research designs can provide solid evidence for a causal
relationship. This understanding implies that, as opposed
to a single test, a theory requires a number of tests from
different research designs. We might assert that whereas
theory is critically necessary, too many theories might be
harmful. It is probably the case that the gain from an incomplete
test of a new theory is less than the gain from a new
test of an existing theory.

Economics provides a useful example. The question
of whether attending college increases income is one of
long-standing interest to economists. The theory behind the
question is relatively simple. Although I hesitate to state that
the causal hypothesis that college leads to higher incomes is
definitively settled, a review of the many different research
designs used makes a convincing case for a causal effect. If all
of the researchers conducting these studies had been told by
reviewers that new theory was needed, little progress would
have been made.

When we overvalue novel theories, we tend to dismiss
attempts to answer old questions with new research designs.
We can value papers with new theories and little or no empirics.
We also can value papers with little in the way of new theory
but that present novel research designs that provide new
empirical evidence about causal relationships. We could argue
convincingly that both topics require such attention that it
may be difficult to present both novel theory and empirics
in the same paper. Currently, I would state that, in general,
a paper that does not engage in new theory development will
have a difficult time being published in a top journal. I don’t
think that is healthy. If we really want researchers to clearly
establish causal relationships that is often worth doing
alone in a single paper.

In my (and Luke’s) home discipline of political science, I have frequently seen reviewers at top journals suggesting rejection for papers because they don’t think the theoretical contribution is novel enough, even if the research design is compelling. (I am not talking about reviews for my own work either, but that of my much more capable colleagues who have discussed their reviews with me.) But journals seem to be okay with papers that propose new theories with no empirical tests whatsoever. Weird, isn’t it?

I am not saying pure theory papers shouldn’t be published—quite the contrary in fact. What makes sense is some division of labor in the discipline. I recognize the importance of pure theory papers. I also recognize the importance of compelling empirical work that offers a new and credible test of an existing theoretical claim. The usual refrain that I hear when I say this is that “top economics journals don’t seem to have this problem,” and with that I agree. I wonder why there is such a difference.

I agree with pretty much everything else in Luke’s paper too. It is part of a symposium on whether “big data,” “causal inference,” and “formal theory” are conflicting trends, an obviously ridiculous proposition, but one that triggered some nice essays by the contributors.

Share